Page images
PDF
EPUB

the conclusions.

But our minds seem dry | life changes, when external interests cease and unsatisfied. In that case we have the to excite, when the apathy to surroundings intellectual part of Belief, but want the emotional part.

That belief is not a purely intellectual matter is evident from dreams, where we are always believing, but scarcely ever arguing; and from certain forms of insanity, where fixed delusions seize upon the mind and generate a firmer belief than any sane person is capable of. These are, of course, "unorthodox" states of mind; but a good psychology must explain them, nevertheless, and perhaps it would have progressed faster if it had been more ready to compare them with the waking states of sane people.

Probably when the subject is thoroughly examined, "conviction" will be proved to be one of the intensest of human emotions, and one most closely connected with the bodily state. In cases like the Caliph Omar it governs all other desires, absorbs the whole nature, and rules the whole life. And in such cases it is accompanied or preceded by the sensation that Scott makes his seer describe as the prelude to a prophecy :

which belongs to the old begins, all at once, and to the wonder of later friends, who cannot imagine what is come to him, the grey-headed man returns to the creed of his youth.

The explanation of these facts in metaphysical books is very imperfect. Indeed, I only know one school which professes to explain the emotion, as distinguished from the intellectual element in belief. Mr. Mill (after Mr. Bain) speak; very instructively of the "animal nature of belief," but when he comes to trace its cause, his analysis seems, to me at least, utterly unsatisfactory. He says that "the state of belief is identical with the activity or active disposition of the system at the moment with reference to the thing believed." But in many cases there is firm belief where there is no possibility of action or tendency to it. A girl in a country parsonage will be sure "that Paris can never be taken," or that "Bismarck is a wretch," without being able to act on these ideas or wanting to act on them. Many beliefs, in Coleridge's happy phrase, slumber in the "dormitory of the mind; they are present to the consciousness, but they incite to no action. And perhaps Not spoke in word, nor blazed in smoke, But borne and branded on my soul." Coleridge is an example of misformed mind in which not only may "Faith" not A hot flash seems to burn across the brain. produce "works," but in which it had a Men in these intense states of mind have tendency to prevent works. Strong conaltered all history, changed for better or victions gave him a kind of cramp in the worse the creed of myriads, and desolated will, and he could not act on them. And or redeemed provinces and ages. Nor is in very many persons much-indulged conthis intensity a sign of truth, for it is pre-viction exhausts the mind with the atcisely strongest in those points in which tached ideas; teases it, and so, when the men differ most from each other. John time of action comes, makes it apt to turn Knox felt it in his anti-Catholicism; Igna- to different, perhaps opposite, ideas, and tius Loyola in his anti-Protestantism; and to act on them in preference. both, I suppose, felt it as much as it is possible to feel it.

"At length the fatal answer came, In characters of living flame,

Once acutely felt, I believe it is indelible; at least, it does something to the mind which it is hard for anything else to undo. It has been often said that a man who has once really loved a woman never can be without feeling towards that woman again. He may go on loving her, or he may change and hate her. In the same way, I think experience proves that no one who has had real passionate conviction of a creed, the sort of emotion that burns hot upon the brain, can ever be indifferent to that creed again. He may continue to believe it, and to love it; or he may change to the opposite, vehemently argue against it, and persecute it. But he cannot forget it. Years afterwards, perhaps, when

As far as I can perceive, the power of an idea to cause conviction, independently of any intellectual process, depends on three properties.

1st. Clearness. The more unmistakable an idea is to a particular mind, the more is that mind predisposed to believe it. Ia common life we may constantly see this. If you once make a thing quite clear to a person, the chances are that you will almost have persuaded him. Half the world only understand what they believe, and always believe what they understand.

2nd. Intensity. This is the main cause why the ideas that flash on the minds of seers, as in Scott's description, are believed; they come mostly when the nerves are exhausted by fasting, watching, and longing; they have a peculiar brilliancy,

and therefore they are believed. To this cause I trace too my fixed folly as to Bridgwater. The idea of being member for the town had been so intensely brought home to me by the excitement of a contest, that I could not eradicate it, and that as soon as I recalled any circumstances of the contest it always came back in all its vividness.

3rd. Constancy. As a rule, almost every one does accept the creed of the place in which he lives, and every one without exception has a tendency to do so. There are, it is true, some minds which a mathematician might describe as minds of "contrary flexure," whose particular bent it is to contradict what those around them say. And the reason is that in their minds the opposite aspect of every subject is always vividly presented. But even such minds usually accept the axioms of their district, the tenets which everybody always believes. They only object to the variable elements; to the inferences and deductions drawn by some, but not by all.

4thly. On the Interestingness of the idea, by which I mean the power of the idea to gratify some wish or want of the mind. The most obvious is curiosity about something which is important to me. Rumours that gratify this excite a sort of half-conviction without the least evidence, and with a very little evidence a full, eager, not to say a bigoted one. If a person go iato a mixed company, and say authoritatively that the Cabinet is nearly divided on the Russian question, and that it was only decided by one vote to send Lord Granville's despatch," most of the company will attach some weight more or less to the story without asking how the secret was known. And if the narrator casually add that he has just seen a subordinate member of the Government, most of the hearers will go away and repeat the anecdote with grave attention, though it does not in the least appear that the lesser functionary told the anecdote about the Cabinet, or that he knew what passed at it.

Of course, I need not say that this "quality" peculiarly attaches to the greatest problems of human life. The firmest convictions of the most inconsistent answers to the everlasting questions "whence?" and whither?" have been generated by this "interestingness" without evidence on which one would invest a penny.

In one case, these causes of irrational conviction seem contradictory. Clearness, as we have seen, is one of them; but obscurity, when obscure things are interesting, is a cause too. But there is no real difficulty here. Human nature at different times exhibits contrasted impulses. There is a passion for sensualism, that is, to eat and drink and a passion for asceticism, that is, not to eat and drink: so it is quite likely that the clearness of an idea may sometimes cause a movement of conviction, and that the obscurity of another idea may at other times cause one too.

These laws, however, are complex,can they be reduced to any simpler law of human nature? I confess I think that they can, but at the same time I do not presume to speak with the same confidence about it that I have upon other points. Hitherto I have been dealing with the common facts of the adult human mind, as we may see it in others and feel it in ourselves. But I am now going to deal with the "prehistoric" period of the mind in early childhood, as to which there is necessarily much obscurity.

My theory is, that in the first instance a child believes everything. Some of its states of consciousness are perceptive or presentative,- that is, they tell it of some heat or cold, some resistance or non-resistance then and there present. Other states of consciousness are representative,— that is, they say that certain sensations could be felt, or certain facts perceived, in time past or in time to come, or at some place, no matter at what time, then and there out of the reach of perception and sensation. In mature life, too, we have these presentative and representative states in every sort of mixture, but we make a distinction between them. Without remark and without doubt, we believe the "evidence of our senses," that is, the facts of present sensation and perception; but we do not believe at once and instantaneously the representative states as to what is non-present, whether in time or space. But I apprehend that this is an acquired distinction, and that in early childhood evheery state of consciousness is believed, whe ther it be presentative or representative.

And the interest is greater when the news falls in with the bent of the hearer. A sanguine man will believe with scarcely any evidence that good luck is coming, and a dismal man that bad luck. As far as I can make out, the professional" Bulls" and "Bears " of the City do believe a great deal of what they say, though, of course, there are exceptions, and though neither the most sanguine "bull" nor the most dismal "bear" can believe all says.

Certainly at the beginning of the "his-and believe with no kind of difficulty toric" period we catch the mind at a pe- future facts as well as past? riod of extreme credulity. When memory begins, and when speech and signs suffice to make a child intelligible, belief is almost omnipresent, and doubt almost never to be found. Childlike credulity is a phrase of the highest antiquity, and of the greatest present aptness.

So striking, indeed, on certain points, is this impulse to believe, that philosophers have invented various theories to explain in detail some of its marked instances. Thus it has been said that children have an intuitive disposition to believe in "testimony," that is, in the correctness of statements orally made to them. And that they do so is certain. Every child believes what the footman tells it, what its nurse tells it, and what its mother tells it, and probably every one's memory will carry him back to the horrid mass of miscellaneous confusion which he acquired by believing all he heard. But though it is certain that a child believes all assertions made to it, it is not certain that the child so believes in consequence of a special intuitive predisposition restricted to such assertions. It may be that this indiscriminate belief in all sayings is but a relic of an omnivorous acquiescence in all states of consciousness, which is only just extinct when childhood is plain enough to be understood, or old enough to be remembered.

If on so abtruse a matter I might be allowed a graphic illustration, I should define doubt as "a hesitation produced by collision." A child possessed with the notion that all its fancies are true, finds that acting on one of them brings its head against the table. This gives it pain, and makes it hesitate as to the expediency of doing it again. Early childhood is an incessant education in scepticism, and early youth is so too. All boys are always knocking their heads against the physical world, and all young men are constantly knocking their heads against the social world. And both of them from the same cause, that they are subject to an eruption of emotion which engenders a strong belief, but which is as likely to cause a belief in falsehood as in truth. Gradually under the tuition of a painful experience we come to learn that our strongest convictions may be quite false, that many of our most cherished ones are and have been false; and this causes us to seek a "criterion which beliefs are to be trusted and which are not; and so we are beaten back to the laws of evidence for our guide, though, as Bishop Butler said, in a similar case, we object to be bound by anything so "poor."

That it is really this contention with the world which destroys conviction and which causes doubt is shown by examining the cases where the mind is secluded from the Again, it has been said much more world. In "dreams," where we are out plausibly that we want an intuitive ten- of collision with fact, we accept everydency to account for our belief in memory. thing as it comes, believe everything and But I question whether it can be shown doubt nothing. And in violent cases of that a little child does believe in its memo-mania, where the mind is shut up within ries more confidently than in its imagina- itself, and cannot, from impotence, pertions. A child of my acquaintance cor- ceive what is without, it is as sure of the rected its mother, who said that "they most chance fancy, as in health it would should never see" two of its dead brothers be of the best proved truths. again, and maintained, "Oh yes, mamma, we shall; we shall see them in heaven, and they will be so glad to see us." And then the child cried with disappointment because its mother, though a most religious lady, did not seem exactly to feel that seeing her children in that manner was as good as seeing them on earth. Now I doubt if that child did not believe this expectation quite as confidently as it believed any past fact, or as it could believe anything at all, and though the conclusion may be true, plainly the child believed not from the efficacy of the external evidence, but from a strong rush of inward confidence. Why, then, should we want a special intuition to make children believe past facts when, in truth, they go farther

And upon this theory we perceive why the four tendencies to irrational conviction which I have set down survive, and remain in our adult hesitating state as vestiges of our primitive all-believing state. They are all from various causes "adhesive states states which it is very difficult to get rid of, and which, in consequence, have retained their power of creating belief in the mind, when other states, which once possessed it too, have quite lost it. Clear ideas are certainly more difficult to get rid of than obscure ones. Indeed, some obscure ones we cannot recover, if we once lose them. Everybody, perhaps, has felt all manner of doubts and difficulties in mastering a mathematical problem; at the time, the difficulties seemed as real as the

er conviction than the evidence justifies.
If we do, since evidence is the only crite
rion of truth, we may easily get a taint of
error that may be hard to clear away.
This may seem obvious, yet if I do not
mistake, Father Newman's" Grammar of
Assent" is little else than a systematic
treatise designed to deny and confute it.
3. That if we do, as in life we must
sometimes, indulge a "provisional enthu-
siasm," as it may be called, for an idea,-
for example, if an actor in the excitement
of speaking does not keep his phrases to
probability, and if in the hurry of emo-
tion he quite believes all he says, his plain
duty is on other occasions to watch him-
self carefully, and to be sure that he does
not as a permanent creed believe what in
a peculiar and temporary state he was led

problem, but a day or two after he has mastered it, he will be wholly unable to imagine or remember where the difficulties were. The demonstration will be perfectly clear to him, and he will be unable to comprehend how any one should fail to perceive it. For life he will recall the clear ideas, but the obscure ones he will never recall, though for some hours, perhaps, they were painful, confused, and oppressive obstructions. Intense ideas are, as every one will admit, recalled more easily than slight and weak ideas. Constantly impressed ideas are brought back by the world around us, and if they are so often, get so tied to our other ideas that we can hardly wrench them away. Interesting ideas stick in the mind by the associations which give them interest. All the minor laws of conviction resolve themselves to say he felt and to feel. into this great one: "That at first we Similarly, we are all in our various believe all which occurs to us that after-departments of life in the habit of assumwards we have a tendency to believe that ing various probabilities as if they were which we cannot help often occurring to certainties. In Lombard Street the dealus, and that this tendency is stronger or ers assume that "Messrs. Baring's acweaker in some sort of proportion to our inability to prevent their recurrence." When the inability to prevent the recurrence of the idea is very great, so that the reason be powerless on the mind, the consequent conviction" is an eager, irritable, and ungovernable passion.

[ocr errors]

If this analysis be true, it suggests some lessons which are not now accepted.

1. They prove that we should be very careful how we let ourselves believe that which may turn out to be error. Milton says that "error is but opinion," meaning true opinion," in the making.” But when the conviction of any error is a strong passion, it leaves, like all other passions, a permanent mark on the mind. We can never be as if we had never felt it. "Once a heretic, always a heretic," is thus far true, that a mind once given over to a passionate conviction is never as fit as it would otherwise have been to receive the truth on the same subject. Years after the passion may return upon him, and inevitably small recurrences of it will irritate his intelligence and disturb its calm. We cannot at once expel a familiar idea, and so long as the idea remains its effect will remain too.

2. That we must always keep an account in our minds of the degree of evidence on which we hold our convictions, and be most careful that we do not permanently permit ourselves to feel a strong

ceptance at three months' date is sure to be paid," and that "Peel's Act will always be suspended at a panic." And the familiarity of such ideas makes it nearly impossible for any one who spends his day in Lombard Street to doubt of them. nevertheless, a person who takes care of his mind will keep up the perception that they are not certainties.

But,

Lastly, we should utilize this intense emotion of conviction as far as we can. Dry minds, which give an intellectual 66 assent to conclusions which feel no strong glow of faith in them, often do not know what their opinions are. They have every day to go over the arguments again, or to refer to a note-book to know what they believe. But intense convictions make a memory for themselves, and if they can be kept to the truths of which there is good evidence, they give a readiness of intellect, a confidence in action, a consistency in character, which are not to be had without them. For a time, indeed, they give these benefits when the propositions believed are false, but then they spoil the mind for seeing the truth, and they are very dangerous, because the believer may discover his error, and a perplexity of intellect, a hesitation in action, and an inconsistency in character are the sure consequences of an entire collapse in pervading and passionate conviction.

From The Cornhill Magazine. LADY ISABELLA.

PART II.

CHAPTER III.

As I drove home, strangely enough, I met the ladies on their afternoon walk. Mrs. Spencer was in advance as usual, talking rapidly and with animation, while Lady Isabella lagged a step behind, pausing to look at the ripe brambles and the beautiful ruddy autumn leaves.

"Just look what a bit of colour," she was saying when I came up; but Mrs. Spencer's mind, it was evident, was full of other things.

"I wonder how you can care for such nonsense," she said; "I never saw any one so unexcitable. After me fussing myself into a fever, to preserve you from this annoyance! and I knew it would be too much for you

66

[ocr errors]

Hush!" said Lady Isabella, emphatically, and then Mrs. Spencer perceived the pony carriage for the first time, and restrained herself. She changed her tone in a moment, and came up to me with her alert step when I drew the pony up.

66

What a nice afternoon for a drive," she said; "have you been at Royalborough is there anything going on? I have dragged Isabella out for a walk, as usual much against her will."

"I have been to make a call," I said, "on a poor invalid, the wife of Major Bellinger."

[blocks in formation]

"If it was very good of me, I have met with a speedy reward," said I, "for I have quite fallen in love with her and her daughter. They are coming to me on Saturday-if Mrs. Bellinger is able for afternoon tea."

"I know exactly the kind of person," said Mrs. Spencer, nodding her head. "Ah, my dear Mrs. Musgrave, you are always so good, and so

1

stood that this had something to do with the commission she had given me. And I

was so foolish as to think she had divined my thoughts, and had fixed upon Edith, by instinct, as an obstacle in her way.

66

Never mind the daughter," I said hastily, "but do come on Saturday afternoon, and see if I am not justified in liking the mother. I daresay they are not very rich, but they are not unpleasantly poor, or, if they are, they don't make a show of it; and a little society, I am sure, would do her all the good in the world."

This time Lady Isabella looked so intently at me, that I ventured to give the smallest little nod just to show her that I meant her to come. She took it up in a moment. Her face brightened all over. She made me a little gesture of thanks and satisfaction. And she put on instantly her old laughing, lively, satirical air.

"Of course we shall come," she said, "even if this lady were not sick and poor. These qualities are great temptations to us, you are aware; but even if she were just like other people, we should come."

Well, Isabella!" said Mrs. Spencer, "you who are so unwilling to go any where!" but of course she could not help adding a civil acceptance of my invitation; and so that matter was settled more easily than I could have hoped.

I saw them the next day-once more by accident. We were both calling at the same house, and Lady Isabella seized the opportunity to speak to me. She drew me apart into a corner, on pretence of showing me something. "Look here," she said, with a flush on her face, "tell me, dɔ you think me a fool - -or worse? That is about my own opinion of myself."

66

"No," I said, "indeed I don't. I think you are doing what is quite right. This is not a matter which concerns other people, that you should be guided by them, but yourself."

"Oh, it does not concern any one very much," she said, with a forced laugh. "I am not so foolish as to think that. It is a mere piece of curiosity-folly. The fact is, one does not grow wise as one grows old, though of course we ought. Andhe is really to be there on Saturday? Despise me, laugh at me, make fun of me! -I deserve it, I know."

Easily taken in," she was going to say, "He is really to come I hope," I said but I suppose I looked very grave, for she it faltering, with a sense of fright at my stopped. own temerity; and Lady Isabella gave me "Is the daughter pretty, too?" said a doubtful half-suspicious look as she left Lady Isabella: a flush had come upon her me. Now that it had come so near I grew face, and she looked at me intently, wait- alarmed, and doubted much whether I ing, I could see, for a sign. She under-should have meddled. It is very trouble

« PreviousContinue »